Skip to main content

Main menu

  • Home
  • Issues
    • Issue in progress
    • Issues by date
  • Sections
    • Editorial
    • Review
    • Research
    • Commentary
    • Psychopharmacology for the Clinician
    • Letters to the Editor
  • Topic Collections
  • Instructions for Authors
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission checklist
    • Editorial policies
    • Publication fees
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Dr. Francis Wayne Quan Memorial Prize
    • Open access
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • About
    • General information
    • Staff
    • Editorial Board
    • Contact
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC

User menu

Search

  • Advanced search
JPN
  • CMAJ JOURNALS
    • CMAJ
    • CMAJ Open
    • CJS
    • JAMC
JPN

Advanced Search

  • Home
  • Issues
    • Issue in progress
    • Issues by date
  • Sections
    • Editorial
    • Review
    • Research
    • Commentary
    • Psychopharmacology for the Clinician
    • Letters to the Editor
  • Topic Collections
  • Instructions for Authors
    • Overview for authors
    • Submission checklist
    • Editorial policies
    • Publication fees
    • Submit a manuscript
    • Dr. Francis Wayne Quan Memorial Prize
    • Open access
  • Alerts
    • Email alerts
    • RSS
  • About
    • General information
    • Staff
    • Editorial Board
    • Contact
  • Subscribe to our alerts
  • RSS feeds
  • Follow JPN on Twitter
Editorial

“Mental illness is like any other medical illness”: a critical examination of the statement and its impact on patient care and society

Ashok Malla, Ridha Joober and Amparo Garcia
J Psychiatry Neurosci May 01, 2015 40 (3) 147-150; DOI: https://doi.org/10.1503/jpn.150099
Ashok Malla
From the Department of Psychiatry, McGill University, Montréal, Que, Canada (Malla, Joober) and the Centre des Services Santé et Sociaux, Laval, Que., Canada (Garcia).
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • For correspondence: [email protected]
Ridha Joober
From the Department of Psychiatry, McGill University, Montréal, Que, Canada (Malla, Joober) and the Centre des Services Santé et Sociaux, Laval, Que., Canada (Garcia).
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
Amparo Garcia
From the Department of Psychiatry, McGill University, Montréal, Que, Canada (Malla, Joober) and the Centre des Services Santé et Sociaux, Laval, Que., Canada (Garcia).
  • Find this author on Google Scholar
  • Find this author on PubMed
  • Search for this author on this site
  • Article
  • Responses
  • Metrics
  • PDF
Loading

The nature of mental illness has been the subject of passionate discussion throughout history. In ancient Greece Plato,1,2 promoting a mentalist definition of mental illness, was the first to coin the term “mental health,” which was conceived as reason aided by temper and ruling over passion. At around the same time, Hippocrates,3 taking a more physicalist approach, defined different mental conditions as a variety of imbalances between different kinds of “humours.” Griesinger4,5 almost 2 centuries ago was the first to state that “mental illness is brain illness,” an expression that has provided a strong impetus to the more recent medical conception of mental illness. The substantial progress accomplished in genomics and brain imaging in the last few decades made biological psychiatry stronger than ever and contributed to the reification of mental disorders as illnesses of the brain. The almost exclusively biogenetic conceptual framework for understanding mental illness has acquired a hegemony that has influenced mental health practitioners while also influencing campaigns designed to improve public attitudes toward the mentally ill. As a result, the statement “mental illness is like any other illness” has become almost axiomatic and, therefore, by definition it embodies an accepted truth not in need of a proof.

This view of mental illness is presented for better acceptance of the mentally ill by the public and of treatment by those experiencing mental illness and is indeed based on accumulated, albeit limited, knowledge in the neurobiology of mental disorders. However, anything that reaches axiomatic proportions needs a serious examination. In this editorial we examine the reasons underlying this perspective, its consequences and the evidence to support or refute its continued justification. We then present a position that we believe best fits the current state of knowledge and is closest to clinical realities and public perceptions of mental illnesses.

What does the statement actually imply?

The statement that “mental illness is like any other medical illness” implies that mental illness has a biological basis just like other medical illnesses and should be treated in the public’s eye in a similar manner. The purpose of this article is not to present a philosophical or ideological argument in favour of or against a biological basis explaining mental illness, but rather to examine the clinical and public utility of presenting a dominant neurobiological model of mental illness to patients, their families and the public at large.

Illness, pathophysiology and the “self’’

To understand the justification of equating mental and medical disorders, a comparison often made between type 2 diabetes and mental disorders, especially schizophrenia, other psychoses and depression, is worth examining in some detail. Diabetes, although very complex, is understood as the result of dysfunctional glucose metabolism related to absolute or relative insufficiency of insulin signalling. This dysfunctional metabolism is the consequence of endogenous predispositions, such as hereditary diathesis, and environmental factors, including personal choices, such as poor diet and sedentary life style. Therefore, by improving glucose metabolism, either through medication, insulin replacement or changes in lifestyle, positive health outcomes can be expected. Diabetes is diagnosed by confirming high levels of fasting glucose and other related biochemical markers of glucose metabolism. Further, the cascade of its effects on other systems (e.g., cardiovascular, central nervous system) are, or could be, well explained on the basis of physiologic mechanisms. They can also be prevented/treated by better and early control of diabetes. All through this, however, the patient is aware of the nature of his or her problems, including personal choices, and diabetes generally does not affect his or her day-today thinking, behaviour or perception. Except for mental health complications due to neurologic illnesses (e.g., delirium in the context of severe metabolic complications, depression as a consequence of awareness of the life and death implication of the disorder, abnormal perceptions in the case of some neurologic conditions), it can be stated that somatic illnesses, such as diabetes do not usually alter the core self of a person substantially. More importantly, the model of attribution presented to the patient is congruent with the scientific “facts,” thereby making it easier for the person as well as society to accept the condition.

Mental disorders, on the other hand, affect the very core of one’s being through a range of experiences and phenomena of varying severity that alter the individual’s thinking, perception and consciousness about the self, others and the world. This is seen to an extreme degree with more serious mental disorders, such as psychoses and bipolar disorders, but to a lesser albeit significant degree with anxiety, mood, eating and other psychiatric disorders. Emotion, perception, thought and action are the essence of human identity and the concept of “self,” and these are the prime domains altered in mental disorders. The precise definition of what constitutes the self and whether the location of a state of self is a material reality in the brain, its form and the brain-related factors that influence it are deeply philosophical issues,6,7 but not the subject of this editorial. Suffice it to say that factors involved in increasing the risk for mental disorders are endogenous (genetics is recognized as a major contributor to most mental disorders) as well as environmental, much like most medical disorders. Psychological deprivation and trauma, social defeat and isolation, poverty and poor family environment are but some of the environmental factors that have been reported to increase the risk for mental disorders. In addition to changes at the physiologic level, common to somatic and mental disorders the latter encompass changes in one’s definition of “self,” and are not situated outside the “self.” It can even be argued that in the absence of any substantiated biological marker for mental disorders (only 1 has been included in the recent DSM-5: orexin change in narcolepsy),8 the hallmark defining features of mental disorders, at least for now, remain the changes in how the patients feel, think and act and how these changes affect their relation to themselves and to others.

As a first corollary of this definition, contrary to medical conditions where restoring dysfunctional physiologic mechanisms is the main target of therapeutic interventions, this is only 1 part of the therapeutic interventions for mental disorders. The primary focus of therapeutic interventions in mental disorders is helping the patient to feel better and interact more adaptively with his or her social and physical environments. Although there is little doubt that all medical conditions require psychological attention, mental health interventions focus primarily on achieving a positive change in feeling, self-esteem, mood, perceptions, thoughts and action — all changes in the “self” that are not primarily targeted in the treatment of medical conditions. Different models of psychological and social interventions are the main ingredients for these desired changes in the self.

A second corollary of this definition is the fact that mental health is very laden with values, not because scientific factors are lacking, but because values become of the utmost importance — more so than for medical disorders — when we deal with the self and its restoration. While somatic illnesses such as diabetes are primarily defined and shaped by biologically discernible facts, values do play a certain role but do not define the disorder. Societal and personal values are important in the treatment of most medical disorders, but acquire paramount importance in the case of mental disorders. Societal and cultural values even define variations in diagnoses over time and across geographic locations. Compulsory treatments, a particularity in the mental health field, are a strong testimony of how mental health can interfere with the self and how the personal values of the patient can clash with the societal values, thus necessitating legal, value-laden mitigation.

Neurobiology and experience of mental illness

Advances in neurosciences have surely given us much better biological mechanistic explanations of many of the uniquely human cognitive, emotional and conative functions, such as memory, thinking, perception, mood and action. This knowledge has informed us that many mental illnesses derive their vulnerability from underlying biological variations. However, we are far from being able to explain in neurobiological terms many of the behaviours and experiences that constitute the core presentations of mental disorders. Even if neurobiology one day were to provide better explanations of the workings of the brain, more elaborately explain the role of genes in increasing the risk for mental illness and the mechanisms behind complex human behaviour, one would still need to understand the experiences of patients with different forms of mental illness in psychological terms, as recently described by Kendler9 so eloquently. By equating mental illness with any medical illness and, therefore, situating it in an organ within the human biology and not recognizing its unique nature in the way it affects the “self” cannot be justified on the basis of current state of knowledge nor may it serve our patients and society well, as we explain in the rest of this editorial.

Mental illness and the utility of explanatory models

Indeed, it is envisaged that putting mental illness on the same footing as medical illness, society will understand it better and not react negatively toward those with mental illnesses. It is hoped that as a result those with mental illness may face less social stigma — a major obstacle to people seeking and/or receiving help — and reducing stigma may help individuals regain eventual acceptance by society as productive members. Interestingly, the public’s explanatory models of mental illness do not follow this narrative and, on the contrary, the public have multiple models of explaining mental illness varying across cultures and times.

One needs to ask the pragmatic question of whether the strategy of using a biogenetic model of mental illness and equating it with medical illness has actually helped. There are 2 areas worthy of examination in this regard.

Explanatory models, stigma and society

The first is to examine the effect of the statement, “mental illness is like any other medical illness,” on social stigma toward people with mental illness. As indicated previously, implicit in the axiomatic statement is a primarily biological origin of the behaviour and suffering that characterize mental illness. Let us examine the evidence in this regard. In the last decade or 2, biogenetic attribution of all mental disorders, having acquired a hegemoneous status10 has been used primarily to inform campaigns for reducing stigma and promoting better acceptance of mental illness and the people with mental illnesses by society.11,12 Several well-conducted studies have concluded, almost uniformly, that this strategy has not only not worked, but also may have worsened public attitudes and behaviour toward those with mental illnesses. Investigations of stigma have shown that those who consider mental disorders as primarily attributable to biological forces, just like other medical disorders, while absolving the mentally ill person of responsibility for their behaviour and actions, tend to feel less optimistic about their ability to get better and function well, are less accepting of them and feel less positively toward them.13–16 In a review of the literature related to the concept of mental illness being like any other illness, Read and colleagues17 reported that biogenetic causal theories and diagnostic labelling as illness are both positively related to perceptions of dangerousness and unpredictability and to fear of and desire for social distance. The attitudes investigated in these studies are reflected in individuals’ responses to whether they would live next door to, socialize or make friends with or have a close relative get married to a person described as being mentally ill. There is also evidence to suggest that biogenetic explanatory models may have negative consequences for those with mental illness in terms of their implicit self concept and explicit attitudes, such as fear.18 Further, campaigns to reduce stigma that encourage people to think about mental illness as simply another form of medical illness have produced results that show effects to the contrary. For example, a recent study showed that over a 10-year period of deliberate use of the biogenetic explanatory model for campaigning to reduce stigma has resulted in worsening of most, if not all, aspects of public attitudes toward individuals with mental illnesses.19,20 The strength of these perhaps counterintuitive findings comes from the fact that these studies were adequately designed, well powered and, most importantly, replicated in several countries (e.g., United States, Britain, Germany) with very similar results. It is acknowledged that these relatively negative attitudes may be particularly stronger in relation to certain forms of mental illness (e.g., psychosis, manic depressive illness) and addictions.

Explanatory models of mental illness and the mentally ill person

Another domain — perhaps the most important — of examination is the individual with mental illness. In clinical practice, telling patients that their presenting mental illness is like any other medical illness may initially reassure some and assist them in accepting to take medication, especially during the distressing acute phases of a serious mental disorder. They or their families may welcome a simple explanation for encouraging them to accept treatment, which in many cases includes medication. While this strategy can achieve something very important in acute crisis-like situations, it may become problematic, if persistent over time, in getting individuals to accept other highly effective psychological and social treatments. These latter interventions are highly effective and considerably less noxious than often less effective medications for some forms of mental illness, such as mild to moderate depression, anxiety and eating disorders, and emotional dysregulation associated with several long-standing mental illnesses. Even in the most serious mental disorders, such as psychotic, bipolar and severe major depressive disorders, where medications are invariably an essential part of treatment, psychological and social therapeutic interventions are the essential bridge between pharmacological interventions during the acute crises and the need for their sustained use in the long term while at the same time achieving the essential goals of relief of internal distress, restoration of self and a return to productive social and working lives.

Furthermore, presenting mental illness as any other medical illness often implies a medical treatment (medication in most cases) as the dominant treatment strategy. Patients’ rejection of the treating clinician’s medical illness model is generally described as lack of insight and starts the cycle of nonadherence to medication, which then translates into nonadherence to treatment. In reality, if patients and families are allowed to articulate their attributional models, given credit for their “experiential knowledge” and encouraged to enter into a dialogue with the treating clinician, it is more likely there will be some consensus on acceptance of recommended treatment. This may prevent the cycle of disengagement and decline in the course that follows.

What needs to be done?

In clinical practice, if we are to take seriously the multidimensional goals of providing mental health services, as articulated by those seeking and receiving help for mental illness, clinicians have to work within an attributional model that makes sense to the person receiving service, that can be supported by sound argument and evidence and that provides a framework within which those receiving service and those providing it can share a common language. Such a framework will need to include the biogenetic model of attribution of mental illness as 1 of several parallel and equally authentic social, psychological, environmental and cultural models offered by service providers and researchers (acquired knowledge) as well as those who experience mental illness (experiential knowledge). There is a need to create a common language in order to come to an understanding of the person’s experience and to promote such an understanding among the public at large. Denying the special nature of mental illness is unlikely to achieve these important goals.

Some recent developments, such as the promotion of a recovery model21–23 and the early intervention movement,24,25 may hold more promise in improving both the quality of care and possibly involvement of and improvement in public attitudes. The former has emerged from experiential knowledge and advocacy from service users, supported later by sound qualitative research, whereas the latter has emerged from a combination of a shift in philosophy of delivery of care on the part of service providers, parallel generation of evidence of its effectiveness26,27 and greater acceptance by service users and their families, who have now joined the movement as advocates. A third emerging movement, the concept of positive mental health,28,29 may prove to be effective in combating the negative image of mental illness. This movement promotes and is based on human resilience and positive aspects of the experience of mental illness. There is a burgeoning literature emerging in this field, which may balance the rather deterministic, deficit oriented and largely pessimistic miasma created by using an exclusively biogenetic model to explain mental disorders.

Conclusion and recommendations

Simply seeking an axiom of “mental illness is like any other medical illness” is at best simplifying a complex human problem and at worst doing a major disservice to patients, their families and the mental health field. Our dialogue should incorporate the general complexity of human thinking, behaviour, memories and the idea of self and consciousness, including knowledge emerging from sophisticated biogenetic and social science research while attending to the specific complexities that each of us as human beings carry as part of our life stories. That is true for those receiving and those providing services.

We therefore argue that we should continue to have a social and a professional conversation where we find a proper place for neurobiology, social, cultural and environmental forces, personal histories and the uniqueness of each individual when trying to understand, explain and treat mental disorders while avoiding a simplistic reductionism that may be perceived at best as patronizing but ultimately harmful, even though the intentions may be noble. We propose that future antistigma campaigns should give up the axiom of “mental illness is like any other medical illness” and instead present the complex and multifaceted explanations of mental illness as unique along with the positive aspects as discussed here. These campaigns need to be informed not only by the acquired knowledge of service providers and scientists but equally by the experiential knowledge from service users and their families, taking into consideration new knowledge emerging from fields of recovery, early intervention and positive mental health. For clinicians, it would be equally important to embrace explanatory models of mental illness that are based on evidence in science and to include biogenetic, social and cultural models as well as those told to them by the very people they are trying to serve.

Footnotes

  • Editors’ note: The ideas expressed in this editorial are not necessarily those of the journal. Importantly, JPN continues to focus on publishing “papers at the intersection of psychiatry and neuroscience that advance our understanding of the neural mechanisms involved in the etiology and treatment of psychiatric disorders.”

  • Competing interests: See jpn.ca for R. Joober. None declared by A. Malla or A. Garcia.

References

  1. ↵
    1. Grube G
    .Greek medicine and the Greek genius.Phoenix 1954;8:123–135.
    OpenUrl
  2. ↵
    1. Kenny A
    (1973) The anatomy of the soul: historical essays in the philosophy of mind (Blackwell).
  3. ↵
    1. Lloyd GER,
    2. Chadwick J,
    3. Mann WN
    (1983) Hippocratic writings (Penguin UK), 451.
  4. ↵
    1. Griesinger W
    (1861) Die pathologie und therapie der psychischen krankheiten: für aerzte und studirende (A. Krabbe).
  5. ↵
    1. Menninger K,
    2. Ellenberger H,
    3. Pruyser P,
    4. et al
    .The unitary concept of mental illness.Pastoral Psychol 1959;10:13–9.
    OpenUrl
  6. ↵
    1. Duster T
    .Comparative perspectives and competing explanations: taking on the newly configured reductionist challenge to sociology.Am Sociol Rev 2006;71:1–15.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  7. ↵
    1. Fulford B,
    2. Thornton T,
    3. Graham G
    2006Philosophical outputs in mental health practice and research.Oxford textbook of philosophy and psychiatryOxford University Press111–138.
  8. ↵
    1. Jones PB
    .Adult mental health disorders and their age at onset.Br J Psychiatry Suppl 2013;54:s5–10.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  9. ↵
    1. Kendler KS
    .The structure of psychiatric science.Am J Psychiatry 2014;171:931–8.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  10. ↵
    1. Sass LA
    .‘Schizophrenic person’or ‘person with schizophrenia’? An essay on illness and the self.Theory Psychol 2007;17:395–420.
    OpenUrlCrossRef
  11. ↵
    1. US Department of Health Human Services
    (2003) Achieving the promise: transforming mental health care in america: the president ’s new freedom commission on mental health report (Bethesda, MD).
  12. ↵
    1. Sartorius N
    .Fighting schizophrenia and its stigma. A new world psychiatric association educational programme.Br J Psychiatry 1997;170:297
    OpenUrlFREE Full Text
  13. ↵
    1. Speerforck S,
    2. Schomerus G,
    3. Pruess S,
    4. et al
    .Different biogenetic causal explanations and attitudes towards persons with major depression, schizophrenia and alcohol dependence: Is the concept of a chemical imbalance beneficial?.J Affect Disord 2014;168:224–8.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
    1. Angermeyer MC,
    2. Matschinger H
    .Causal beliefs and attitudes to people with schizophrenia trend analysis based on data from two population surveys in Germany.Br J Psychiatry 2005;186:331–4.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
    1. Dietrich S,
    2. Matschinger H,
    3. Angermeyer MC
    .The relationship between biogenetic causal explanations and social distance toward people with mental disorders: results from a population survey in Germany.Int J Soc Psychiatry 2006;52:166–74.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  14. ↵
    1. Read J,
    2. Law A
    .The relationship of causal beliefs and contact with users of mental health services to attitudes to the ’mentally ill’.Int J Soc Psychiatry 1999;45:216–29.
    OpenUrlPubMed
  15. ↵
    1. Read J,
    2. Haslam N,
    3. Sayce L,
    4. et al
    .Prejudice and schizophrenia: a review of the ‘mental illness is an illness like any other’ approach.Acta Psychiatr Scand 2006;114:303–18.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  16. ↵
    1. Rüsch N,
    2. Todd AR,
    3. Bodenhausen GV,
    4. et al
    .Biogenetic models of psychopathology, implicit guilt, and mental illness stigma.Psychiatry Res 2010;179:328–32.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  17. ↵
    1. Pescosolido BA,
    2. Martin JK,
    3. Long JS,
    4. et al
    .“A disease like any other”? A decade of change in public reactions to schizophrenia, depression, and alcohol dependence.Am J Psychiatry 2010;167:1321–30.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  18. ↵
    1. Mehta N,
    2. Kassam A,
    3. Leese M,
    4. et al
    .Public attitudes towards people with mental illness in England and Scotland, 1994–2003.Br J Psychiatry 2009;194:278–84.
    OpenUrlAbstract/FREE Full Text
  19. ↵
    1. Davidson L,
    2. Strauss JS
    .Beyond the biopsychosocial model: integrating disorder, health, and recovery.Psychiatry 1995;58:44–55.
    OpenUrlPubMed
    1. Whitley R,
    2. Drake R
    .Recovery: a dimensional approach.Psychiatr Serv 2010;61:1248–50.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  20. ↵
    1. Windell D,
    2. Norman R,
    3. Malla AK
    .The personal meaning of recovery among individuals treated for a first episode of psychosis.Psychiatr Serv 2012;63:548–53.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  21. ↵
    1. McGorry PD,
    2. Killackey E,
    3. Yung A
    .Early intervention in psychosis: concepts, evidence and future directions.World Psychiatry 2008;7:148–56.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  22. ↵
    1. Malla AK,
    2. Norman R,
    3. Joober R
    .First-episode psychosis, early intervention, and outcome: What have we learned?.Can J Psychiatry 2005;50:881–91.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  23. ↵
    1. Harvey PO,
    2. Lepage M,
    3. Malla A
    .Benefits of enriched intervention compared with standard care for patients with recent-onset psychosis: a meta-analytic approach.Can J Psychiatry 2007;52:464–72.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  24. ↵
    1. Nordentoft M,
    2. Rasmussen JØ,
    3. Melau M,
    4. et al
    .How successful are first episode programs? A review of the evidence for specialized assertive early intervention.Curr Opin Psychiatry 2014;27:167–72.
    OpenUrlCrossRefPubMed
  25. ↵
    1. Carr A
    .Positive mental health: a research agenda.World Psychiatry 2012;11:100
    OpenUrlPubMed
  26. ↵
    1. Cloninger CR
    .The science of well-being: an integrated approach to mental health and its disorders.World Psychiatry 2006;5:71–76.
    OpenUrlPubMed
PreviousNext
Back to top

In this issue

Journal of Psychiatry and Neuroscience: 40 (3)
J Psychiatry Neurosci
Vol. 40, Issue 3
1 May 2015
  • Table of Contents
  • Index by author

Article tools

Respond to this article
Print
Download PDF
Article Alerts
To sign up for email alerts or to access your current email alerts, enter your email address below:
Email Article

Thank you for your interest in spreading the word on JPN.

NOTE: We only request your email address so that the person you are recommending the page to knows that you wanted them to see it, and that it is not junk mail. We do not capture any email address.

Enter multiple addresses on separate lines or separate them with commas.
“Mental illness is like any other medical illness”: a critical examination of the statement and its impact on patient care and society
(Your Name) has sent you a message from JPN
(Your Name) thought you would like to see the JPN web site.
CAPTCHA
This question is for testing whether or not you are a human visitor and to prevent automated spam submissions.
Citation Tools
“Mental illness is like any other medical illness”: a critical examination of the statement and its impact on patient care and society
Ashok Malla, Ridha Joober, Amparo Garcia
J Psychiatry Neurosci May 2015, 40 (3) 147-150; DOI: 10.1503/jpn.150099

Citation Manager Formats

  • BibTeX
  • Bookends
  • EasyBib
  • EndNote (tagged)
  • EndNote 8 (xml)
  • Medlars
  • Mendeley
  • Papers
  • RefWorks Tagged
  • Ref Manager
  • RIS
  • Zotero
‍ Request Permissions
Share
“Mental illness is like any other medical illness”: a critical examination of the statement and its impact on patient care and society
Ashok Malla, Ridha Joober, Amparo Garcia
J Psychiatry Neurosci May 2015, 40 (3) 147-150; DOI: 10.1503/jpn.150099
Digg logo Reddit logo Twitter logo Facebook logo Google logo Mendeley logo
  • Tweet Widget
  • Facebook Like

Related Articles

  • No related articles found.
  • PubMed
  • Google Scholar

Cited By...

  • 'Delusional consent in somatic treatment: the emblematic case of electroconvulsive therapy
  • Mandating the Spread of Faulty Information: Implications for the Children of the Future
  • Google Scholar

Similar Articles

Content

  • Current issue
  • Past issues
  • Collections
  • Alerts
  • RSS

Authors & Reviewers

  • Overview for Authors
  • Submit a manuscript
  • Manuscript Submission Checklist

About

  • General Information
  • Staff
  • Editorial Board
  • Contact Us
  • Advertising
  • Reprints
  • Copyright and Permissions
  • Accessibility
  • CMA Civility Standards
CMAJ Group

Copyright 2023, CMA Impact Inc. or its licensors. All rights reserved. ISSN 1180-4882.

All editorial matter in JPN represents the opinions of the authors and not necessarily those of the Canadian Medical Association or its subsidiaries.
To receive any of these resources in an accessible format, please contact us at CMAJ Group, 500-1410 Blair Towers Place, Ottawa ON, K1J 9B9; p: 1-888-855-2555; e: [email protected].
View CMA's Accessibility policy.

Powered by HighWire